Rethinking Liber­alism: Do We Need a New Liber­alism of Fear?

Shutter­stock

Liber­alism is a political persuasion devoted to the pursuit of human flour­ishing. It demands that, at a minimum, every indi­vid­ual must be per­mit­ted to write its own life’s story, unob­structed by fear, cruelty, or crush­ing intru­sion. In light of new endogenous and external threats to free societies, how can we prevent fear from becoming the dominant public sentiment? In his essay, Amichai Magen argues for a “New Liber­alism of Fear.”

Liber­alism – a term long subjected to much conceptual-stretching and abuse – is a political persuasion devoted to the pursuit of human flour­ishing through the exercise of individual liberty, economic openness, limited and egali­tarian government, and the rule of law. At its core resides an insis­tence upon the sublime worth and dignity of each and every individual human being, and ultimately of life itself.

Liberalism’s overriding political mission is to secure the essential condi­tions necessary for the fullest possible expression of that sublime individual worth, and the unique human potential imbued in it. It therefore rejects any political doctrine or system of government that does not respect the difference between the spheres of the personal and those of the state, between areas of individual private life (including family and communal life) and that of public authority.

At a minimum, liber­alism demands, every individual must be permitted to write her own life’s story – unobstructed by fear, cruelty, or crushing intrusion – as is compatible with the like freedom of every other individual. The life story written by the individual may amount to a heroic drama, a bitter-sweet comedy, or a tragic flop. Liber­alism does not insist on a happy ending; but it does insist that it must, to a meaningful extent, be her story to write for herself.

Liber­alism, in other words, is an essen­tially modern political quest for an existence in which human beings need not fear annihi­lation, arbitrary violence, unnec­essary coercion, or violation of what Isaiah Berlin – in his Oxford Don’s conspicuous under­statement — described as “a certain minimum area of personal freedom which must on no account be violated.”[1]

The Liber­alism of Fear

This “Liber­alism of Fear” – which Montesquieu and Constant already alluded to, but which was only explicitly illumi­nated and explored in Judith Shklar’s brilliant 1989 chapter by the same name – is not the only species in the liberal tradition worth mining for ideas for twenty-first century liberal renewal.[2] Shklar recog­nizes this herself, referring to other types of liber­alism, notably “the liber­alism of natural rights” and “the liber­alism of personal devel­opment”, that differ from the liber­alism of fear.[3]

One more caveat is noteworthy before I proceed to outline a case for a “New Liber­alism of Fear”, as one avenue for liberal renewal. “Fear” is, on its face, an unattractive prop for the liberal persuader. The smell of fear is normally under­stood to be odious. Hope, unicorns, and the promise of free love are, under­standably, the preferred marketing tools of the political soothsayer.

Amichai Magen is a Senior Lecturer and Director of the Program on Democ­ratic Resilience and Devel­opment at the Lauder School of Government, Diplomacy, and Strategy, IDC (Herzliya), Israel. 

The liber­alism of fear, conse­quently, suffers from an inherent marketing problem. In this sense it is a little like Isaiah Berlin’s notion of “Negative Freedom” – wise but not catchy.[4] The average consumer of political ideas will find no fluffy comfort in the liber­alism of fear. What distin­guishes it from those other types of liber­alism, Shklar herself tells us, is that it is entirely “nonutopian”.[5]

The liber­alism of fear stares terror squarely in the face and shudders. It is starkly aware of the depths of depravity human beings are capable of and the scale of savagery and destruction that can be inflicted upon us fragile humans, partic­u­larly by insti­tu­tion­alized cruelty.

The liber­alism of fear is defined by a certain terrible modesty of expec­ta­tions. It is the liber­alism of damage control, and of the good enough to get by. It is the liber­alism of avoiding Auschwitz-Birkenau, the Soviet Gulag, and, in our own time, the brutal­ization of the Yazidis, the starvation of the Yemenites, or the prison camps of North Korea and Xinjiang. Its primary – and in some respects primal – aim is to remind us to focus on avoiding the very worst that can happen to us, not assume that it somehow won’t happen, or be tempted by the alluring but false utopian promises of a world free of tragedy.

A Liber­alism of Damage Control

The “New Liber­alism of Fear” begins with the shaking-off of the historical amnesia that has pervaded our culture since 1989. Complacent, smug, and more than a little naïve, we slumbered under the warm duvet of post-1989 triumphalism. Confident that the end of history had arrived, that the arc of the moral universe was inexorably bending towards justice, and that the rest of the world would inevitably converge around an ever-expanding, ever-deepening Liberal Inter­na­tional Order under­written by the land of the free and the home of the brave.

Under the influence of this Fukuyama Coma, liber­alism was permitted to stagnate and decay. Ironi­cally, we liberals committed the cardinal sin of Marxism, the sin of historical deter­minism. We drifted, and largely squan­dered the hard won peace dividend that came from victory in the mighty ideological struggles against Fascism, Nazism, and Soviet Communism over the course of the bloody twentieth-century. We neglected to nurture the virtues, values, and insti­tu­tions upon which modern liberal democ­racies depend for their survival – active and engaged citizenship, effective statehood and robust public insti­tu­tions, genuine democ­ratic account­ability to ensure govern­ments act in the interest of the majority, and the rule of law to constrain those who would wield coercive political, economic, and cultural power.

In the process, we left many of our fellow citizens behind – foolishly forgetting the first principle of liberal modernity, namely that the consent of the governed is the only solid basis for a functioning democ­ratic order. We pretended that the dark sides of global­ization were either not there, did not matter too much (that they would soon melt away under the forces of liberal conver­gence), or that they could be effec­tively managed by the invisible hand of markets alone. We neglected to keep up with accel­er­ating connec­tivity, complexity, and disruptive, anxiety-inducing techno­logical change. We failed to generate convincing liberal solutions to large emerging threats – Chinese author­i­tar­i­anism, environ­mental damage, uncon­trolled migration, failed states, nuclear prolif­er­ation, pandemics, unaligned Artificial Intel­li­gence, and a degraded infor­mation ecology that risks oblit­er­ating our ability to agree on basic scien­tific and historical facts.

The “New Liber­alism of Fear” demands a strongly developed sense of historical memory, and an histor­i­cally-informed imagi­nation about the future of humanity. It would therefore bring history back in, in three distinct ways:

First, to paraphrase Hal Brands and Charles Edel, it would insist that an under­standing of tragedy remains indis­pensable to the conduct of politics, state­craft, and the preser­vation of world order.[6] If we forget the inherent fragility of liberal orders – and the need to contin­u­ously defend, preserve, and update them – we will invariably continue to sink into neglect and decline.

Making the Case for the Morality of Liberal Orders

Second, it would invest real time and energy in making the case for the morality (yes, morality, not just efficiency) of liberal orders. It would proudly champion and celebrate the aston­ishing human progress achieved since the birth of the liberal era, and especially over the past several decades, across all the main indicators of human material wellbeing, where liberal values and insti­tu­tions took root. It would highlight the truly stunning 3,000 percent increase in real GDP for the poorest people since 1800, and how in the past three decades most of this “Great Enrichment” has occurred not in “white America” or Western Europe, but in liber­al­izing Latin America, Eastern Europe, China, India, and increas­ingly Africa.[7]

The “New Liber­alism of Fear” would actively seek to make living and succeeding gener­a­tions grasp the true meaning – in terms of human lives saved, improved, enriched, and liberated – of the following statistics: In 1950 global average life expectancy was less than 30 years, today it is 72.6. In 1950 global child mortality was 24 percent – meaning that nearly one in four babies died before their fifth birthday – today it is 4 percent. In 1950 the percentage of the world’s population living in extreme poverty was 63.5 percent, today it is less than 9. And in 1950 only 10 percent of the world’s population lived in democ­racies, today – even after a decade and a half of a global democ­ratic recession – 56 percent of human beings live in democ­racies.[8] This is an aston­ishing record of material and moral progress. It is imperfect, incom­plete, and fragile, but it is also incal­cu­lably good and deserving of our gratitude, protection, and continued development.

Lastly here, the “New Liber­alism of Fear” would make the case that rethinking liber­alism must involve an expansion of our historical imagi­na­tions not just with reference to the past – with its litany of successes and failures, triumphs and crimes – but towards the future. Rethinking liber­alism, as Toby Ord’s wonderful dedication in his book The Precipice puts it, must involve a commitment: “To the hundred billion people before us, who fashioned our civilization; To the seven billion now alive, whose actions may determine our fate; To the trillions to come, whose existence lies in the balance.”[9]

Living in Fear Makes Us Unfree

The question of whether or not we live in a free society, the “New Liber­alism of Fear” under­stands, is to a great extent a matter of collective psychology. “We fear a society of fearful people” as Shklar puts it, because systematic mass fear makes human freedom impos­sible.[10] If we live in fear, we are funda­men­tally unfree.

High-tech tyranny of the type offered by the Chinese Communist Party might be more “efficient” than the politics of imper­fection, individual choice, and uncer­tainty offered by liber­alism. But what is the use of such efficiency to the human spirit? What is the point of it if it would make us into a gargantuan colony of fearful, cowering slaves? Similarly, what is the point of our human civilization if we make our planet uninhab­itable or permit unaligned AI to run amok and hurl us into slavery or even extinction? The New Liber­alism of Fear stares into that soulless abyss of possible dystopian traps and shudders. It refuses to go gentle into those night­marish nights. It rages against the dying of the light.

Liberals have feared different things at different times and so have striven to create and adapt political orders to tackle a succession of changing fears. Early modern liber­alism – and there existed no liber­alism in the pre-modern world – emerged from the chaos and carnage of religious intol­erance and war. Fear of religious coercion is the cradle of modern liber­alism. Gradually, over the course of the sixteenth and seventeen centuries, we discovered that toler­ation was superior to the cruelty of religious fanaticism.

Then, in a second grand wave of compe­tition over the nature of political order, the principles and insti­tu­tions of limited and egali­tarian government proved to provide superior advan­tages – military, economic, scien­tific, and in terms of personal happiness – compared with Absolutism. Once Leviathan was firmly estab­lished, we discovered that it could devour us with greater ease and system than pre-modern author­ities ever could. We therefore gradually then invented various mecha­nisms for taming Leviathan. We call these, variably, civil and political rights, the rule of law, consti­tu­tion­alism, feder­alism and, eventually, modern repre­sen­tative democracy. Those societies who adopted and practiced these mecha­nisms sensibly achieved greater power, prosperity, and dynamism.

And from the turn of the twentieth century, our liberal orders – national, regional, and inter­na­tional – evolved again because we came to fear poverty, total war, and the rise of collec­tivist total­i­tarian ideologies and states. Spurred by these fears, nation-state based, market-based liberal democ­racies contested, and eventually defeated, their imperial, fascist, Nazi, and Soviet Communist adversaries.

Viewed through this prism, contem­porary liberal orders are essen­tially a “triple-distilled” package of normative and insti­tu­tional goods, accrued over centuries in a series of historical compe­ti­tions where “the liberal solution” eventually emerged victo­rious, having proved superior to its competitors at providing physical and ontological wellbeing. Our modern forms of liberal order – containing the genome of toler­ation, bounded-statehood, consent-based repre­sen­tative democracy, and the market-economy – are the outcome of repeated successful contes­tation and selection. Liberal order has survived and prolif­erated because it has repeatedly proven superior in providing physical and ontological security. At the same time, the evolu­tionary logic is a cold one. Unless liberal orders are able to once again compete and demon­strate their superi­ority, we should expect anti-liberal order-contes­tation and defec­tions to increase.[11]

The Fear of Human Redundancy

What do we fear most today? In some places we still fear what Locke, Constant, Mill, Popper, Hayek, Arndt, Berlin, Solzhen­itsyn and Shklar feared in the past – the unequal power of the author­i­tarian and predatory state over the individual. And yet, the “New Liber­alism of Fear” would admit – with a pinch of skepticism mixed with cautious satis­faction – that in most contem­porary societies, most of the time, it is not state power that we fear most. Indeed, in many areas of limited statehood – in Iraq and Libya, Syria, Somalia, Congo and Haiti, to name but a few sorry examples – it is the conse­quences of the absence of effective statehood that people fear most.

Ultimately, what we – in what until recently was lightly called “The Free World” – now fear most is a coming human redun­dancy. We fear physical redun­dancy as the result of existential catastrophes – demographic decline, climate extinction, unrecov­erable civiliza­tional collapse, or unrecov­erable dystopia – at the hands of nature or anthro­pogenic threats. We fear the complete loss of economic and political human agency to uncon­trolled forces of financial markets, Big-Tech algorithms, and ubiquitous corporate and state surveil­lance. We fear metaphysical redun­dancy in the loss of meaning, purpose, belonging and attachment, not so much to indus­trial-age alien­ation but to digital era machines and synthetic biology. We even fear epistemic redun­dancy, in that very soon AI and Deep Fake technologies may very well extin­guish ordinary people’s ability to handle the accel­er­ating complexity of the world or tell the difference between fact and conspiracy theory.

The challenge before us liberals today is nothing less than to stem and reverse human redun­dancy. We require a new human­istic liber­alism that is at once true to the core values of the liberal tradition and provides superior outcomes of human flour­ishing to those proffered by our author­i­tarian and collec­tivist adversaries.

The challenge posed by the “New Liber­alism of Fear” is serious, possibly existential, but it is not entirely grim. As Bernard Williams observed in his own meditation upon Judith Shklar’s text: “the liber­alism of fear is not confined to uttering warnings and reminders. If indeed primary freedoms are secured, and basic fears are assuaged, then the atten­tions of the liber­alism of fear will move to more sophis­ti­cated concep­tions of freedom…[12] Confronting our era’s worst fears squarely, resolutely, and creatively is arguably our best path forward to once again reach a liber­alism of hope.

 

[1] Isaiah Berlin, “Two Concepts of Liberty”, in Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969) pp. 118–172 at pg. 122.

[2] On Montesquieu’s reference to the human need for personal security as a precon­dition for political freedom see: Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, tr. Cohler, Miller, and Stone (Cambridge, 1989), p. 157. Benjamin Constant also reflects on the relationship between security, fear, and liberty in his 1819 lecture The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with That of the Moderns. Judith N. Shklar, “The Liber­alism of Fear”, in Liber­alism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy L. Rosenblum (Harvard 1989) pp. 21–38.

[3] Shklar, ibid. at p. 26–27.

[4] Berlin, Supra, note 1.

[5] Ibid. at p. 26.

[6] See: Hal Brands and Charles Edel, The Lessons of Tragedy: State­craft and World Order (Yale University Press, 2019).

[7] For the full data see The Maddison Project Database 2020 (available: https://www.rug.nl/ggdc/historicaldevelopment/maddison/releases/maddison-project-database-2020?lang=en). For a summary and analysis see: Deidre N. McCloskey, Bourgeois Equality: How Ideas, Not Capital or Insti­tu­tions, Enriched the World (Chicago University Press, 2016); Steven Pinker, Enlight­enment Now: The Case for Reason, Science, Humanism, and Progress (Viking, 2018).

[8] Figures drawn from Our World in Data (available: https://ourworldindata.org/a‑history-of-global-living-conditions-in-5-charts). On life-expectancy see: https://ourworldindata.org/life-expectancy#:~:text=The%20divided%20world%20of%201950,achieved%20in%20a%20few%20places.

[9] Toby Ord, The Precipice: Existential Risk and the Future of Humanity (Hachette, 2020).

[10] Shklar, Supra, note 3, at p. 29.

[11] See: Amichai Magen, Liberal Order in the Twenty-First Century: Searching for Eunomia Once Again, 139/2–4 Journal of Contextual Economics (2019) 271–284.

[12] Bernard Williams, In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument (Princeton University Press, 2005) p. 60.